Heidegger, fenomenologia, hermenêutica, existência

Dasein descerra sua estrutura fundamental, ser-em-o-mundo, como uma clareira do AÍ, EM QUE coisas e outros comparecem, COM QUE são compreendidos, DE QUE são constituidos.

Página inicial > Léxico Alemão > Dahlstrom (2001:270-272) – ser-com-os-outros (Mitsein, Mitdasein)

Dahlstrom (2001:270-272) – ser-com-os-outros (Mitsein, Mitdasein)

domingo 11 de fevereiro de 2024

destaque

[…] A afirmação de Kant   de que "os seres humanos existem como fins em si mesmos" é suposto referir-se precisamente ao que Heidegger designa como "cuidado", nomeadamente, "que o que está em jogo para o ser humano é o seu próprio ser". No entanto, o objetivo de Kant não é apenas sublinhar a distinção entre coisas e pessoas, mas também apontar para "um mundo de inteligências". Do mesmo modo, o conceito de cuidado de Heidegger, precisamente ao determinar o mundo da preocupação, também inclui aquilo a que ele chama "solicitude", "cuidar dos outros" ou, em suma, "estar-com-os-outros". "O mundo do ser-aí é ser-com-os-outros" (SZ   118). É certo que, tanto nas Conferências Prolegômenos como em Ser e Tempo, ao abordar "quem é o ser-no-mundo", Heidegger rejeita a ideia de que a resposta a esta questão tenha qualquer "avaliação moral  " (GA20   337, 389, 391). No entanto, a referência à determinação de Kant dos seres humanos como "propósitos em si mesmos" faz mais do que meramente sugerir que a descrição de Heidegger do "ser-com-os-outros" como um aspecto central do ser-aí pretende recapitular, em certo sentido, o que de outra forma é visto como fundamental para a ética. De fato, nalgumas das passagens mais exasperantes de Ser e Tempo, Heidegger pede aos seus leitores que diferenciem o "propósito puramente ontológico" da sua interpretação de uma "crítica moralizante do ser-aí quotidiano", apenas para conceder mais tarde que "uma concepção ôntica específica da existência genuína, um ideal   factual do ser-aí", está subjacente à interpretação. [SZ 167, 310]

original

“We designate as care the basic type of being of an entity that is such that what is at stake for it in its being is this being itself’ (L 220). Heidegger did not   himself draft an ethics in any traditional sense. Hence, it is worthy of note when he remarks that this phenomenon of care is precisely what Kant has in mind in working out the basis for the so-called humanistic formulation of the categorial imperative: “human beings exist [271] as purposes in themselves.” [1] This remark presents Heidegger with the opportunity to point out, once again, the necessity of the metacategorial distinction. According to Heidegger, Kant attempts in vain with standard ontological categories to present the distinctively human manner of being. Kant’s attempt fails, not because the concepts are old or traditional, but because such categories are suited to things in nature other than human beings. [2]

There is an additional reason why Heidegger’s reference to Kant’s efforts to provide a foundation for the categorial imperative is particularly instructive in this connection. Kant’s claim that “human beings exist as purposes in themselves” is supposed to refer precisely to what Heidegger designates as “care,” namely, “that what is at stake for the human being is his or her being itself.” Kant’s aim, however, is not only to emphasize the distinction between things and persons, but also to point to “a world of intelligences.” [3] Similarly, Heidegger’s concept of care, precisely in determining the world of concern, also includes what he dubs “solicitude,” “caring-for-others,” or, in short, “being-with-others.” [4] “The world of being-here is being-with-others” (SZ 118). To be sure, in the Prolegomena Lectures as in Being and Time, in the course of addressing “who being-in-the-world is,” Heidegger rejects the idea   that the answer in this connection has any “moral evaluation” (P 337, 389, 391). Nevertheless, the reference to Kant’s determination of human beings as “purposes in themselves” does more than merely suggest that Heidegger’s account of “being-with-others” as a central aspect of being-here is meant to recapitulate in some sense what otherwise is viewed as foundational for ethics. Indeed, in some of the more exasperating passages [272] of Being and Time, Heidegger pleads with his readers to differentiate the “purely ontological purpose” of his interpretation   from a “moralizing critique of everyday being-here,” only to concede later that “a specific ontic conception of genuine existence, a factual ideal of being-here,” does underlie the interpretation. [5]

[DAHLSTROM  , Daniel O. Heidegger’s concept of truth. Cambridge: Cambridge university press, 2001]


Ver online : Daniel Dalhstrom


[1L22of;GP 195. See, too, Heidegger’s rejection of distinct philosophical disciplines such as logic, ethics, aesthetics, and philosophy of religion in PAA 172.

[2This point is iterated in the summer of 1927 (GP 201-209) and becomes the basis for the lectures in the summer of 1930: Vorn Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit, ed. Hartmut Tiegen, GA 31, second edition (1994), 220, 238, 246, 255. Heidegger can point to the use of the category of causality to elaborate the meaning of ‘freedom’ and to the conformity of the table of categories of freedom in the Kritik der praktischen Vernunft to the table of categories in the Kritik der reinen Vernunft.

[3Immanuel Kant, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (1785), in Kants Werke, vol. 4 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1968), 462, 453.

[4‘Solicitude’ is not an adequate translation of ‘Fürsorge,’ a term used to signify everything from a mother’s loving care for her child to social welfare. Yet, while a little-used synonym for ‘anxiety’ or ‘worry,’ ‘solicitude’ can connote concern directed at others. ‘Being solicitous of others’ has the added advantage, like ‘Fürsorge,’ of being used widely, e.g., for loving attention and for intrusiveness or pushiness. ‘Solicitude is the Vulgate translation of ‘merimna’ in Greek; cf. SZ iqq 11. 1.

[5SZ 167, 310. For a development of this ethical accent, see Frederick Olafson, Heidegger and the Ground of Ethics (New York: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1998). See, too, Christopher Fynsk’s discussion of being-with in his Heidegger: Thought and Historicity, expanded edition (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell Univ. Press, 1993), 28-54.